Introduction
So, I’ve just begun to read Joe Morris’ Perpetual Frontier: The Properties
of Free Music, a summary of which can be found here.
While I’m still in the early stages, it’s got me thinking about how to organize
a group of musicians to play free music, and I’m also seeing how there’s an
underlying philosophy that can be useful in communicating some of Morris’
ideas. If I’m feeling up to it, I’ll provide commentary on Morris, perhaps on a
per chapter basis. However, mostly I want to hash out my own ideas.
Suppose we
begin with a group of musicians, and our objective is to get them to play “free
music.” To make this as concrete as possible, let us suppose that in a month’s
time, they will have to play a concert of “free music.” Moreover, suppose that
all of the musicians in question are well versed in at least one genre of
non-free music, but are relative neophytes in all forms of free music. How
would we get these musicians to succeed in their concert?
It’s
tempting to start devising lots of exercises, a la Tom Hall.
I can’t stress how important those exercises are, and how much I’ve loved going
through them. However, how would we know that these exercises have been
effective in producing a successful concert? What we need is a better grasp of
the concept of a successful free music performance. An exercise would be effective
just in case it promoted that.
I think that philosophy can help on
this front. In what I hope will be a series of posts, I’ll show how we can get
a clearer concept of a successful free
music performance. Today, I’ll focus just on musical performances, temporarily bracketing the success or freedom of such performances.
I suggest that we think of musical
performances as systems constituted
by mechanisms. Let’s first understand
systems and mechanisms more generally (§1),
and then discuss how a musical performance is a special case of systems and
mechanisms (§2).
Third, I’ll consider objections to this view, and offer my replies to them (§3).
Finally, I’ll briefly summarize and highlight the practical payoff of this view
(§4).
1. Systems and mechanisms
My goal for today is to show that musical performances can
be regarded as mechanistic systems. Before
talking about musical performances, let me describe some general features of
mechanistic systems. Philosophers and scientists in the relevant disciplines
have described many biological, psychological, technological, social, and
cultural phenomena as mechanistic systems. While they have different views
about what constitutes a mechanism, the general idea about mechanistic systems is
this:
(General Idea) Many systems exhibit
certain properties because of the
properties, activities, and organization of the systems’ parts.
For instance, the
heart pumps blood because of the properties, activities, and organization of
the ventricles and atria.
For now, I’ll
rely on your native intuitions as to what constitutes a part-whole
relationship, property, activity, and organization. However, I do want to spend
a bit more time on a seemingly banal word: the use of “because” in the General
Idea, as mechanistic systems have a special “because”-structure. In his book, Explaining
the Brain, (which looks at mechanisms in neuroscience), Carl Craver discusses
this “because”-structure, and dubs it the Mutual
Manipulability Condition (MMC).
That may
sound scary, but the idea is pretty straightforward: in mechanistic systems,
two kinds of changes must be possible:
(1)
Changes to the
properties, actions, or organization of the parts must be capable of changing
the properties of the system, and
(2)
Changes to the
properties of the system (or whole) must be capable of changing the properties,
actions, or organization of its parts.
For instance, think about the neuroscience of reading. Here
the system is a person reading and the parts are the relevant parts of the
brain. The MMC states that:
(1)
Had the relevant
brain regions been different, then a person’s way of reading would have been
different, and
(2)
Had a person’s way of reading been different,
then the relevant brain regions would have been different.
An example of the first manipulation or intervention is brain
surgery or the use of certain mind-altering drugs that affect reading. An
example of the second would be altering the speed at which words come across a
screen in order to change how neurons fire.
2. Musical performance as a mechanistic system
Now, all of this seems pretty far removed from music, right?
Wrong! I'd like to suggest that musical performances are usefully thought of as
mechanistic systems. Recall that the ultimate goal is to specify what is
constitutive of a successful free music
performance. However, for today, I want to make the argument that all musical performances (successful or
otherwise, free or otherwise) are mechanistic systems.
If I’m
going to establish that claim, I need to show that: (§2.1)
a musical performance is a system composed of parts and (§2.2)
the system and parts satisfy the Mutual Manipulability Condition.
2.1. Musical performances are systems composed of parts
I first want to show that musical performances is an
application of the General Idea. I propose that we simply think of a musical
performance as a system.
Now clearly, such a performance has
many potential properties it can assume. Call these performance properties. Some performance properties are emotive, e.g. performances can be
uplifting, dreadful, banal, intense, soothing, etc. Performances properties can
also be of a more formal variety,
e.g. performances can be in a particular time signature, key, exhibit
particular chord progressions, melodies, harmonies, dynamics, etc. (More on
performance properties at a later date.)
Moreover, performances are composed
of parts. I suggest that we take performers
as our primary parts. So a musical performance is a mechanistic system just in
case the following is true:
A musical performance exhibits
certain properties (e.g. being uplifting, banal intense, etc.) because of the
properties, activities, and organization of the performers.
This seems eminently plausible. Moreover, it’s a good thing
to impress upon our hypothetical musicians with their hypothetical deadline,
for it stresses the responsibility
that they have for the musical
performance.
2.2. Musical performances and performers are mutually manipulable
However, if I really want to make my case for musical
performances as mechanistic systems, I need to show that musical performances
satisfy the MMC. Now, one requirement of the mutual manipulability condition seems
relatively uncontroversial, namely this:
(1)
Had the
performers’ properties, actions, and organization been different, then the
musical performance would have exhibited different properties.
The most obvious evidence for this is that performers play
differently to create different musical pieces. However, the other requirement
of the mutual manipulability condition is trickier:
(2)
Had the musical
performance exhibited different properties, then the performers’ properties,
actions, and organization would have been different.
For those who are interested in the puzzle that arises with
(2), go to the Appendix. For the rest of you, let me
skip straight to its solution: sometimes, one
subset of actions, properties, and/or organization of some performers can
change another subset of such actions, properties, and/or organization only via the performance properties.
For instance, imagine that all of
the members of a group are playing the same rhythmical motif, until the drummer
suddenly changes her rhythm. The drummer’s rhythmical change is not
self-contained; it also changes the performance’s overall rhythmical
properties. In particular, there will be greater rhythmical complexity than if
all of the performers had continued to play the same motif. This complexity can
then elicit a change in other players: do they maintain the complexity, or do
they alter their rhythm to either enhance or diminish that complexity? In this
way, one set of actions, properties,
and organization belonging to the performers can change another subset of actions,
properties, etc. only via the
performance properties.
It will be
useful to economize our language at this point. We have three crucial elements
in this structure:
(A)
Interventions: the
actions, properties, and/or organization that change the performance
properties;
(B)
Responses: The
actions, properties, and/or organization that are changed via the performance
properties; and
(C)
The performance properties.
Using these labels we can summarize our view. An event is a
musical performance if and only if it possesses performance properties such
that:
- Interventions are possible.
- It is possible
for interventions to affect responses only
via performance properties.
3. Objections, with replies
Now, you may not be
convinced. In particular, I will address two potential objections. First,
doesn’t this way of thinking of musical performance rob it of its emotive and
non-analytical qualities (§3.1)? Second, what happens with solo performances (§3.2)?
3.1. Isn’t this soulless?
Even
seeing the sentence “Musical performances are mechanistic systems” may offend
the sensibilities of those who think of music in more emotive, non-analytical
terms. I offer four replies. First, the terminology of systems and mechanisms
is something that I inherit from philosophers of science, e.g. Carl Craver and Peter
Machamer, but very little hangs on this choice of
words. I welcome alternative terminology that is less offensive to the
touchy-feelies of the world J. For instance, since biologists frequently
regard organisms as mechanistic systems composed of parts (organs, cells, and
molecules), I could just as easily describe my view as thinking of music as an
“organic whole,” which perhaps sounds less incongruous to those who dislike
talk of mechanistic systems. Second, recall that the ultimate goal is to
clarify the concept of a successful free
music performance. Whatever the value of thinking emotively and
non-analytically, it is frequently an ineffective tool when clarity is our aim.
Third, it should be recognized that the fact that a system can be explained
mechanistically is entirely compatible with taking emotions and non-discursive
modes of thought as real phenomena. Indeed, the psychology of emotion rests on
exactly this assumption. Finally, let’s first see how the whole approach works,
and then decide if it’s inadequate to the task of clarifying a successful free
music performance.
3.2. Solo performances
I have argued that performances are
mechanistic systems only if it’s possible for one subset of performers’
actions, properties, and organization (interventions)
to affect another subset of performers’ actions, properties, and organization (responses) only via performance-level
properties. At first blush, this would appear to require every performance to
involve at least two performers. “However,”
my critic continues, “that is surely incorrect, as there are solo performances.” Hence, a critic has
a seemingly plausible argument that solo performances are not mechanistic
systems.
However,
this rests on a confusion of what interventions and responses are. They are,
first and foremost, sets of actions,
properties, and (modes of)
organization. They are not sets of performers.
So multiple actions, properties, or modes of organization are needed for a
musical performance; multiple performers
are not needed.
Once this is appreciated, it is clear that
solo performances satisfy our two conditions for a musical performance.
Specifically, an event is a solo musical
performance if and only if the event
involves only a single performer and a set of performance properties such
that:
(1)
Interventions are
possible.
(2)
Interventions that
affect responses only via performance
properties are possible.
As before, condition (1) remains
uncontroversial, as a soloist who played very different things would create
very different performance properties. Given what we’ve said, (2) should seem
unremarkable to anyone who has performed solo. For instance, suppose that our
drummer from before is now a soloist who changes his rhythm mid-performance.
Then clearly he has intervened on the musical properties. There is clearly a
change in the performance’s properties, for its form now includes a rhythm
change. However, the drummer can now respond: after the rhythm change, the
drummer can decide to continue with the new rhythm, return to the previous rhythm,
etc. and presumably this can be in response to the performance’s formal
structure. Hence nothing about solo performances undermines my account of
musical performances.
4. The payoff thus far
So, why go through all of this? Recall the larger objective.
We begin with a bunch of non-free musicians and are trying to get them produce
a successful free music performance.
Thus far, we’ve bracketed success and freedom, and simply tried to articulate
what a musical performance is. Our
musicians have thus come to see that a musical performance is a system with a
particular set of properties, namely performance properties that can the
musicians can intervene upon and to
which they can respond.
Now, let me
suggest where I want to go next: different genres
or kinds of music can be
individuated by the norms that govern their interventions, responses, and
performance properties. Hence, we can start to get a sense of free music in virtue of its distinctive
configuration of these three elements.
Appendix: Some puzzles about responses
Above, I noted that the following is a tricky claim to
establish, but didn’t want to belabor people with the details:
Had the musical performance exhibited different
properties, then the performers’ properties, actions, and organization would
have been different.
To see the difficulty with this case, we’ll need to say more
about what we mean by manipulability
in MMC. Here is the way that Jim Woodward (roughly)
characterizes the idea:
An ideal intervention I on X
with respect to Y is a change in the value of X that changes Y,
if at all, only via the change in X.
In our particular case, X
is the performance properties, Y is
the performers’ properties, actions, and organization. So we’re looking for
some ideal intervention I such that:
I is a change in the performance’s
properties that changes the
performers’ properties, actions, and organization, if at all, only
via the change in the
performance’s properties.
Now, the tricky bit is this. If this is going to be
practical advice for performers, then
the ideal intervention, I, should be something that they can do. However, that would mean that I is a performer’s action. But that would mean that performances change performers’
actions only via changing performers’ actions, which makes the performance’s
properties totally irrelevant.
The
solution to this puzzle emerges from the fact that performances are composed of
more than one action, property,
and/or mode of organization. Consequently, one action, property, or mode of
organization can serve as an ideal intervention
(I) on a performance property (X), while another such action, property, or mode of organization (Y) can be a response to that performance property. That is the view I presented
above.